Masks and Paradox, Passion and Joy: An Analysis of Chesterton and Nietzsche



Download 38.33 Kb.
Date03.05.2016
Size38.33 Kb.
Stephen Conway

1992
Masks and Paradox, Passion and Joy:

An Analysis of Chesterton and Nietzsche
Imagine the lame giant of the Victorian age stumbling about in the darkness, wrestling with an unseen opponent. It pries the crushing grip of a hand from its throat only to discover the hand is its own. Imagine two explorers on opposites sides of a great ocean. Anchors are weighed, and each explorer sets out to see just beyond the horizon, to sail beyond the sunset. They collide amidships in the midnight fog and breeze, but they continue their journeys. They reach land, utter words of praise and thanks, plant their flags and claim their claims only to discover that they had each returned to "conquer" their homelands. G.K. Chesterton and Friedrich Nietzsche embarked on cyclical

journeys. Using their explorations in "Orthodoxy" and Beyond Good and Evil, their courses can be mapped toward self discovery. A dynamic relationship exists in examining and understanding their similar philosophical motivations and the resulting overlapping arguments. They both launch scathing attacks on reason; they conceal their ultimate meanings through complexity: one through paradox, the other with the metaphor of the mask; they both advocate the reawakening of a child-like sense of wonder, and ultimately, they found their ethical systems on courage. Using the same philosophical tools, each thinker carves out a completely unique niche into intellectual history: one within the framework of orthodox Christianity, the other as a forefather of modern Existential thought.

Chesterton set "Orthodoxy" in the context of a personal statement of faith and as a retort to Mr. G.S. Street's critique of his earlier work "Heretics." Street claimed that "Heretics" did not provide the reader with a sense of Chesterton's Orthodoxy (Ho11is 8). Orthodoxy
"0perated as an informed yet extremely powerful

Christian apology. Chesterton asked the fundamental

question, "How can we contrive to be at once

astonished at the world and yet at home in it?"

(Chesterton 212).
Chesterton believed that Victorians had lost the ability to experience the wonder of the world and still feel welcomed by it simultaneously. The familiar and the unfamiliar could and should exist without hostility.

This thought made most Victorians shudder, because according to Chesterton, Victorian society had gone mad because his society relied too heavily upon reason. A great

chasm existed between reason and intuition, and Victorians

did not throw many bridges over the darkness to cross the gap (Lea 93). Instead, they wa11owed in reason and it made

them mad. "Imagination does not breed insanity. Exactly what does breed insanity is reason. Poets do not go mad, but chess players do.. ." (Chesterton 219). Mad people held

blindly to a "reasonable" ideology. These ideologies were

fundamentally based upon the denial of the filth and waste in human existence. "They essentially deny human sin, which they can see on the street" (Chesterton 217). Chesterton attacked philosophies that totalize, that essentially made incomprehensible, concepts comprehensible by inscribing them within the bounds of reason.

Nietzsche claimed that all knowledge was falsification. Thought was the supreme act of ego; it was an act of possession. Abstract concepts, people, places became objectified and subject to a rational truth (Nietzsche 23). "Philosophy always creates the world in its own image; it cannot do otherwise" (Nietzsche 16). Beyond Good and Evil was a critique of the rational basis for morality. "Truth" became the great assimilator when it fell prey to reason. Good, evil, and truth were given meaning through reason. Nietzsche began with the question, "Supposing truth were a woman, what then?", because all supposed objective truths would be shaken if this one assertion were "true" (Nietzsche 1). Truth and morality were obsolete because they were reasonable (Nietzsche 12).

Chesterton's attack was not focused at a particular group. He saw emptiness in materialism and Darwinism

which objectified the universe in the term cosmos (Chesterton 22). He also accused modern religions of being spiritually contracted.


"They are universal in the sense that they take one

thin explanation and carry it very far. But a

pattern can stretch forever and still be a small

pattern" (Chesterton 25).

Nietzsche claimed that reason had become

synonymous with nature and that nature taught humanity its need for limitations, its desire for narrowness (Nietzsche 102). The true task of each individual was to break free from such limits. Ironically, Nietzsche himself gladly accepted some limitations, his belief in raw sensibility. "All evidence of truth comes from the senses" (Nietzsche 88). In Chesterton's estimation, Nietzsche's adherence to a doctrine of sensuality made Nietzsche mad.

It was not the limitations that reason imposed upon society to which Chesterton objected most profusely, for he acknowledged that intelligent ideas confine the mind. They forced the mind to operate within a specific framework (Chesterton 226). Reason sought to eliminate doubt, to destroy mystery, and this G.K. Chesterton could not tolerate. The source of Nietzsche's madness was not the fact that he had boxed himself up within an idea, but that the box was absolute and offered no means of escape (Chesterton 229). Chesterton sought to preserve the most profound mystery of the universe through mysticism in order to make everything else logical. Reason was simply a matter of faith.
"To utilize reason at all requires a certain

fundamental faith in a human being's ability to know

something about the objective world; all

intellectual endeavors, not just those involving

Christians, depend on faith" (Hill 232).
In this manner doubt was not destroyed by the Victorians; it was simply misplaced. Victorians doubted Divine reason instead of their own. Rather than doubt modern scientific rational truth, it was easier to call into question a truth beyond human understanding, beyond proof. A sense of powerlessness, paralysis and apathy was the result (Chesterton 235). This same discovery led Nietzsche to believe that philosophy, the tyrannical drive," was killing God and, with God, human passion (Nietzsche 66).

Both Nietzsche and Chesterton agreed that reason was a

tool. Where Nietzsche sought to transcend this tool and be

free, Chesterton attempted to reconcile and re-establish the connection between reason and intuition, between thought and action.


"The modern world much like a madman, has a

proclivity to ignore the complexity of relativity in

favor of the simplicity of singularity" (Hill 242).
In order to communicate the complex relationship between reality and reason, reality and faith, G.K. Chesterton reveled in the power of paradox. Put simply, a paradox was "truth turned on its head" (Hollis 26). In accepting a paradox, one was forced to deal with inherent contradictions without having the ability to synthesize, a quality also characteristic of life. Christianity was at its heart the supreme paradox. Christ himself was fully human and fully divine; the orthodoxy that surrounded his teaching was thus pragmatic and mystical simultaneously. According to Chesterton only Christianity was so steeped in paradox that God was actually able to revolt against Himself asking, "Why have you forsaken me?". "Christianity declared it was a conflict: the collision of two passions apparently opposite" (Chesterton 297). God was distant, separate, unassailable, but with faith in God came a sense of wholeness and universality. The chain of paradoxes was as endless and diverse as life itself. Perhaps "Orthodoxy" itself serves as the best testimony to Chesterton's cyclical use of paradox. He attempted to create heresy and ended advocating orthodoxy (Chesterton 214).

Nietzsche concealed ultimate meanings in his writing in order to prevent his work from being distilled into objective truths. His writing was and continues to be often misunderstood. It resisted all attempts at universal comprehension because it was masked (Nietzsche 229).


"Every profound spirit needs a mask; even more,

around every profound spirit a mask is growing

continually" (Nietzsche 51).
The reader was invited to engage the text only at a tangent to Nietzsche's intentions and ideas: through the mask of harsh language he had donned when writing the book. Thus, communication was a method of concealment as well as a method of relaying basic information (Nietzsche 92). Perhaps Chesterton failed to see the face behind the mask when he questioned Nietzsche's courage and conviction.
"Nietzsche was not at all bold. He never put his

own meaning before himself in bald abstract words...

Nietzsche always escaped a question by a physical

metaphor, like a cheery minor poet. He said 'beyond

good and evil' because he had not the courage to say

'more good than good and evil'.. .Had he faced his

thought without metaphor he would have seen that it

was nonsense" (Chesterton 309).


Ironically, both authors stress the need for courage to enact their moral/philosophical views. Nietzsche's fierce desire not to be understood, even by a formidable mind like Chesterton, was a supreme act of courage. True courage stemmed from an ability to exercise one's Will to Power which was the will of life (Nietzsche 203). The ability to slough off the morality of the herd, Christianity, and act upon one's own will, to freely choose, became more important than what was chosen. "Thus an occasional will to stupidity" (Nietzsche 84). To be a master was to show courage where slaves fell victim to morality because they were too weak or too afraid to live authentically and independently (Nietzsche 209). To live passionately, to authentically relate to other individuals, one must assert one's ego in the interests of self preservation. Most people did not "mature" in this manner. In Nietzche' s estimation "a man's maturity consists in having found again the seriousness of a child at play" (Nietzsche 83). Chesterton was a coward. He could have been a master but became a slave, and a spokesman for other slaves and slavery itself!

For all Nietzsche's rallying cries for courageous action to would be masters, little action resulted. Nietzsche's courage was hollow and ineffectual to Chesterton. He compared Nietzsche to Joan of Arc to prove his point.


"Nietzsche only praised the warrior; she was the

warrior...we know she was not afraid of an army,

while Nietzsche, for all we know, was afraid of a

cow" (Chesterton 247).


Where the will was liberating to Nietzsche, Chesterton found freedom in possessing the courage to accept orthodoxy and 'its manifold paradox. Nietzsche's freedom was ephemeral at ,best. Inherent in the concept of will was a desire for self limitation. A choice, once made, was an acceptance of something and a rejection of everything else. "Art is limitation. The essence of every picture is a frame" (Chesterton 243). In essence, freedom had enslaved itself (Chesterton 240). All choices had the same moral weight if Nietzsche was correct in stating that the choice itself was singularly important. Hitler's decision to commit genocide and a decsion to eat a ham sandwich cannot be separated (Chesterton 246). Change itself had become unchangeable; it had become institutionalized and, thus reified in the Marcusian sense of the word.

Only the bastion of orthodoxy preserved an element of

eternal revolution to Chesterton. In order to accept the

conflicts embedded in the living tradition, Christians must

have courage. They must "seek life in a spirit of furious

indifference to it. Desire life like water but drink death

like wine" (Chesterton 297). He refuted the apathy and resignation of late Victorians like Matthew Arnold by by claiming that the source of their despair was an inability

to find meaning in the universe, a basic lack of courage (Chesterton 362). As a devoted advocate of democracy, he

embraced Nietzsche's comment that democracy was born out of

the Christian tradition as a compliment rather than an

insult. To this he added that tradition and democracy were

merely expressions of the same ideal. Tradition was

democracy extended through time, "the democracy of the dead" (Chesterton 251). Tradition taught Chesterton that humanity had Fallen from Grace. As we were created we were separated from God. We Fell to Earth and with this Fall we became free but obligated to acknowledge an ethical covenant that was broken when we were created. Chesterton's ethical argument was based on a courage of restraint as well as action. Ethics depended on action and inaction. (Chesterton 260). Tradition reminded each generation of its ethical obligation. Each generation, was free, of course, to ignore the teachings of tradition. Understanding and accepting the fact that humanity was separate from God and, thus, ethically fallen and morally responsible was the key to Chesterton's sense of joy.

As a child G.K. discovered ethics, mysticism, and a

sense of adventure through fairy tales (Chesterton 252).

Mothers and fathers were the first source of loving authority and children were protected by their teachings.

He suggested that conversion, acceptance of orthodoxy, was like entering a second Childhood. This echoed Nietzsche's desire to regain" the seriousness of a child at play" with

one great distinction. Catholic doctrine erected walls, but they were the walls of a playground not a prison. Children

were born upside down and Christianity set child-like adults on their feet (Chesterton 363). Joy meant to have the courage to abandon one's self and float with the flux of life, to exult in monotony, to dare to look upon each

experience as if it never happened before and will never

happen again, to laugh and revel in levity. Christianity was a living teacher of joy in the moment and of eternity.

Chesterton thought Nietzsche's greatest fault was his

inability to laugh (Chesterton 364).
"This is the last essential of the Victorian. Laugh

at him as a limited man, a moralist, a

conventionalist, an opportunist, a formalist. But

remember also that he was really a humorist and may

be laughing at you " (Victorian 78).
Both men ardently desired to uncover a true mode of

relation. They were separated by joy and passion. Perhaps

this division can be articulated more clearly using

Chesterton's rediscovery of his own Christian ethic: the sin of suicide and the glory of the martyr. Suicide was the

ultimate act of ego. "The man who kills himself, kills all

men; as far as he is concerned he wipes out the world" (Chesterton 276). Whereas the martyr sacrificed himself for the sake of the world, an act of love, of supreme recognition that something exists outside one's self (Chesterton 277). To Nietzsche, however, martyrdom was a pathetic act of slavery and only suicide brought solace to him. "The thought of suicide is a powerful comfort: it helps one through many a dreadful night" (Nietzsche 91).

Joy and passion do not necessarily oppose one another. Nevertheless, they are separate and distinct modes of relation. Shrouded in complexities, it may well be impossible to tell whether G.K. Chesterton was secretly laughing, beneath his paradoxes, whether Nietzsche was sneering behind his mask.

Works Cited


Chesterton, G.K. G.K. Chesterton: Colected Works. San

Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1986.


---. The Victorian Agein Literature. Notre Dame, Indiana:

University of Notre Dame Press, 1962.


Hill, Kent R. "The Sweet Grace of Reason: The Apologetics

of G. K. Chesterton". Rpt. In The Riddle of Joy.

Michael MacDonald and Andrew A Tadie Eds. Grand Rapids Michigan: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1989.
Hollis, Christopher. G.K. Chesterton. London: Longman,

Greens & Co., 1964.


Lea, F.A. Modern Christian Revolutionaries. Donald Atwater

Ed. New York: The Devin-Adair Co., 1947.


Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. Walter Kaufmann

trans. New York: Random House, 1989.


Share with your friends:




The database is protected by copyright ©essaydocs.org 2020
send message

    Main page