Hume’s Attack on Newton’s Philosophy Eric Schliesser Introduction and Summary



Download 235.38 Kb.
Page1/3
Date25.05.2016
Size235.38 Kb.
#65948
  1   2   3


Hume’s Attack on Newton’s Philosophy
Eric Schliesser
Introduction and Summary

In this paper, I argue that major elements of Hume’s metaphysics and epistemology are not only directed at the inductive argument from design which seemed to follow from the success of Newton’s system,1 but also have far larger aims. They are directed against the authority of Newton’s natural philosophy; the claims of natural philosophy are constrained by philosophic considerations.2 Once one understands this, Hume’s high ambitions for a refashioned ‘true metaphysics’3 or ‘first philosophy’, that is, Hume’s ‘Science of Human Nature’,4 can be seen and evaluated in their proper light.5 Hume has three motives for his attack on Newton: his work is informed by and gives cover to superstitious beliefs; his project is not useful to the public; and its success generates a challenge to the independent authority of philosophy.

This essay consists of five sections in addition to this introduction. First, I discuss Hume’s attitude toward Newton. Newton claims that natural philosophy should be the foundation for other sciences, while in the ‘Introduction’ to the Treatise Hume asserts the supremacy of the ‘science of man’.6 For Hume the human sciences can attain the high epistemic status of ‘proof’, while much of the physical sciences must do with lower forms of ‘probability’. Furthermore, Hume’s ‘rules by which to judge of causes and effects’ do not replicate Newton’s fourth Rule; this opens a gap between the ontologies and methodologies of Newton and Hume. Moreover, Hume’s account of causation is designed to undercut the reductionist bias of natural philosophy. According to Hume the parts of natural sciences that go beyond common life can be evaluated from the point of view of the science of man. I end with remarks on the philosophic origins and significance of Hume’s attack on Newton’s natural philosophy.

I depart from two independent traditions of interpreting Hume. One tradition makes many references to Newton’s influence on Hume.7 On a more detailed level, proponents of this view may call attention to Hume’s ‘rules’,8 his ‘Experiments’ and ‘Anatomy’,9 his method of investigation,10 the application of Newtonian metaphors works (e.g., an ‘attraction’ in the ‘mental world’ on a par with that in the ‘natural world’ – the principles of association are, then, analogous to the laws of motion).11 Hume’s ‘science of man’ is said to be inspired by Newton’s science of nature.12

Hume wants his readers to feel that he is modeling his project on the successes of natural philosophy, exemplified by Newton. In the ‘Introduction’ to the Treatise and more explicitly in the opening pages of EHU,13 Hume suggests that his ‘science of man’ can parallel recent achievements in natural philosophy (especially planetary astronomy). Thus, my claim is not that Newton did not figure importantly in Hume’s philosophy,14 but, instead, that Hume’s project is in many respects more hostile to Newton’s achievements – as available to well-informed eighteenth-century readers – than many recent interpreters have realized.

There is a different tradition that argues Hume simply did not understand Newton. Hume’s philosophy, thus, cannot do justice to Newtonian science.15 Hume’s lack of mathematical competence is said to be a barrier to his understanding of Newton’s mathematical natural philosophy. One finds this attitude behind the cranking of Bayesian machinery in Earman’s attack on Hume’s treatment ‘Of Miracles’.16 However, this tradition begs the question; it takes the authority of ‘science’ for granted in Hume.

Against this second tradition I argue that Hume did understand salient features of Newton’s methodology and position, although in ways often unappreciated by the first tradition mentioned above. For example, in his comments on Newton in the History of England, Hume discerns the (broad) outlines of Newton’s commitment to the method of analysis and synthesis (see Newton’s Opticks, Query 31) and how it differs from Boyle’s methodology.17 So, Hume has a subtle understanding of Newton’s methodology – even if one were to grant that he lacks appreciation of the role of mathematics in Newton’s natural philosophy.18 Leaving open the question whether Hume understood all the details of Newton’s system, Hume’s departures from Newton are best interpreted not as ‘ironic’,19 but as philosophically motivated.

I offer one methodological-historical comment. In the main body of this paper I treat Hume’s philosophic program statically as if there are no changes in the larger aims of his program during the progressive construction of his oeuvre. This presentation allows the argument to be stated in its most extreme and, thus, clearest form. Yet, this needs important qualification on two fronts.

First Newton is never mentioned in the Treatise; only in the ‘Appendix’, which Hume wrote after he had published the first two volumes, does he use the phrase, ‘Newtonian philosophy.’ In contrast to EHU, which has a Newtonian rhetoric, some explicit mention of Newton, and increasing focus on the status of ‘laws’, the Treatise is remarkably unaffected by Newtonian themes, concepts, or methods.20

Second, the changed rhetoric and orientation between Treatise and EHU can be explained, in part, by the timing of both works. When Hume drafted the Treatise while at La Flèche in 1734-1737, Newton’s system was not a ‘settled fact’ – there were serious outstanding empirical issues (regarding shape of the Earth and the lengthening of the pendulum with latitude) that were not decided until French expeditions to Lapland and the Equator.21 Maupertuis’ Sur la figure de la terre appeared in 1738 (it also appeared in English translation that year). Hume’s close friend, Adam Smith, mentions this result as decisive evidence for Copernicanism and the Newtonian system in his ‘History of Astronomy’.22 That same year (1738) Voltaire published his influential piece of Newtonian propaganda Elémens de la philosophie de Newton; an English translation appeared in the same year. I have no idea when Hume became aware of the relevant empirical evidence, but probably not at La Flèche. It is, of course, possible that when back in Britain between the publication of the first two volumes of the Treatise and the drafting of the ‘Appendix’, which was added to the third volume published in November 1740, he became aware of these recent developments.

So, to be clear, when Hume drafted the first two volumes of the Treatise, Continental Cartesians accepted celestial inverse-square gravity, and it was accommodated within various systems (Leibniz, Huygens, Rohault). But outside Britain Hume could have found himself in a large and important company for thinking that the terrestrial (and, thus, universal) gravity part of Newton’s claims was still speculative.23 After 1738, learned opinion moved decisively into Newton’s camp across Europe, and Hume’s increasing employment of Newtonian language and themes reflects this. But while Hume changed his position on some issues, I argue that he held steadfast to some important larger themes. I do not address the possibility that the texts I cite from Hume’s essays and histories might be taken as evidence of a genuine shift in his understanding of and his relationship to Newton. Here these works are merely treated as a rich source in illuminating the intentions of and meaning behind the Treatise and the EHU.24

One may think that the subtitle of the Treatise, ‘Attempt to Introduce the Experimental Method of Reasoning into Moral Subjects’, shows Hume’s self-conscious debt to Newton.25 After 1712 in the context of his polemic with Leibniz, Newton and his followers increasingly refer to his own philosophy as ‘experimental’.26 Even so, Newton always emphasizes that his are Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy.27 The subtitle of the Treatise probably illustrates Hume’s methodological commitment to Boyle.28





The Science of Man as an Attack on Newton’s Foundations

In this section I first introduce a concept, “Newton’s Challenge”, in order to explain why Hume might have thought Newton’s success generates a challenge to the independent authority of philosophy. Second, Hume argues against Newton’s claim of the superiority of natural philosophy, and for the epistemic equality of moral and natural philosophy. Also, I offer evidence for at least two reasons for Hume’s moral hostility to Newton’s project: Hume thinks that Newton’s philosophy gives cover to superstition, and that it is not useful to the public.

The nature of Hume’s ambitions is more evident when we put them in context of a text by Newton widely noted by Hume’s contemporaries.29 A query was added to the first Latin edition of the Opticks (Optice, 1706) by Newton and maintained in subsequent editions that is significant for our purposes: ‘And if, natural Philosophy in all its Parts, by pursuing this Method, shall at length be perfected, the Bounds of Moral Philosophy will be also enlarged. For so far as we can know by natural Philosophy what is the first Cause, what Power he has over us, and what Benefits we receive from him, so far our Duty towards him, as well as that towards one another, will appear to us by the Light of Nature’.30 It accords well with the inductive argument for God’s existence in the General Scholium, added to the second edition (1713) of the Principia: ‘to treat of God from phenomena is certainly a part of natural philosophy’ (emphasis added).31 In Newton’s published works he says, ‘We know [the Deity] only by his most wise and excellent contrivances of things, and final causes.’ For Newton the study of motion, duty, and unchanging, first causes are part of a shared enterprise (see also his claim in the General Scholium that although we will know nothing of God’s substance, we can ‘have ideas of God’s attributes’).32 Newton accords our knowledge of the existence of the Deity a lower epistemic status than the evidence that convinces us of the existence of a (beautiful) systematic arrangement of our solar system and the bodies within it, and the existence of similar such systems at an immense distance. According to Newton ‘these regular motions do not have their origin in mechanical causes’ (General Scholium).33

In order to discuss these passages, I introduce a concept: “Newton’s Challenge”.34 By this I refer to the fact that the authority of natural science is used to settle debates within philosophy. I distinguish among: (NC1) a philosopher claims that natural philosophy must be consulted in the process of doing metaphysics; (NC2) a philosopher claims that natural philosophy is epistemically prior to metaphysics; (NC3) a philosopher appeals to the authority of a natural science which is in some sense (institutionally, methodologically) not philosophy to settle argument over doctrine, method, etc. NC1 has an ancient pedigree; NC2-3 are more prominent after 1700. While it may not have originated with or even been intended by Newton, Newton facilitated “Newton’s Challenge” by allowing Cotes (the editor of the second edition of the Principia) to publish a highly influential, lengthy preface (1713), in which two competing approaches to philosophy, the Scholastic and mechanical philosophy, are severely criticized from the point of view of ‘observations and experiments’.

In the passage from the Opticks Newton claims that natural philosophy can guide the search for first causes, or metaphysics (NC2). Moreover, natural philosophy is clearly the more secure, foundational enterprise to other forms of knowledge (that is, commitment to NC3). Newton’s infamous rejection of hypotheses (General Scholium) is also a version of NC3.

Let us now turn to Hume’s ‘Introduction’ to the Treatise:

’Tis evident, that all the sciences have a relation, greater or less, to human nature; and that however wide any of them may seem to run from it, they still return back by one passage or another. Even Mathematics, Natural Philosophy, and Natural Religion, are in some measure dependent on the science of Man; since they lie under the cognizance of men, and are judged of by their powers and faculties . . . [W]e ourselves are not only the beings, that reason, but also one of the objects, concerning which we reason

.…………………………………

And as the science of man is the only solid foundation for the other sciences, so the only solid foundation we can give this science itself must be laid on experience and observation.35

Hume’s ‘science of man’ either displaces or is a reinterpretation of more traditional metaphysics as the fundamental form of knowledge of the order of things; knowledge of it is required if ‘certainty’ and ‘security’ are possible at all. Hume’s ‘science of man’ is not merely a goal in its own right, interesting as that may be, but may also be requisite to help better understand the other sciences.36 Hume also talks of the ‘changes and improvements we might make in these sciences’.37 Thus, the ‘science of man’ can instruct the other sciences. How this is supposed to work, and in what sense it is a ‘foundation’, is left unclear; maybe this is why Hume employs the more tentative sounding, ‘some measure’.

I do not rehearse Hume’s well-known attack on the argument from design in Section XI of EHU or in the Dialogues here. No doubt Hume is in large part motivated to undercut Newtonian attempts to enlist natural theology in debates over moral philosophy.38 (In the Dialogues, Cleanthes is the spokesperson for this view). Such an enterprise fits squarely in the tradition of physico-theology, popular among Boyle lecturers; these are approvingly mentioned by, for example, the Scottish Newtonian Colin Maclaurin.39 Physico-theology makes natural philosophy a handmaiden to theology. One can interpret Hume as correcting Newton, and the eighteenth-century Newtonian natural religion advocates, on internal “Newtonian” grounds.40 This interpretation underestimates the programmatic ambition of Hume.

For in the Introduction to the Treatise, Hume claims, first, that the ‘science of man’ is the only solid ‘foundation’ for the other sciences; it is the condition of possible certainty and security;41 second that it ‘will not be inferior in certainty’ to other forms of knowledge;42 our knowledge of ‘mental powers and œconomy’ can, despite some practical difficulties, have ‘equal success’ as our knowledge in natural philosophy.43 As Hume says in ‘Of the Balance of Trade’: ‘We need not have recourse to a physical attraction … There is a moral attraction, arising from the interests and passions of men, which is full as potent and infallible.’44

Hume’s ‘Introduction’ to the Treatise, then, signals the start of an ambitious program that departs from Newton’s project. We do not need the perfection of natural philosophy to make progress in moral philosophy. Moreover, Hume indicates that the science of man may be required to make further progress in natural philosophy. Hume makes it clear where his priorities are: ‘Nor ought we to think, that this latter improvement in the science of man will do less honour to our native country than the former in natural philosophy, but ought rather to esteem it a greater glory, upon account of the greater importance of that science, as well as the necessity it lay under of such a reformation.’45 In sum, Hume’s ‘science of man’ is ‘much superior in utility to any other of human comprehension’.46

When Hume comments more directly on Newton, the lack of utility of Newton’s works is an important part of Hume’s analysis: ‘Were we to distinguish the Ranks of Men by the Genius and Capacity more than by their Virtue and Usefulness to the Public, great Philosophers would certainly challenge the first Rank, and must be plac’d at the Top of human Kind. So rare is this Character, that, perhaps, there has not, as yet, been above two in the World, who can lay a just Claim to it. At least, Galilaeo [sic] and Newton seem to me so far to excel all the rest.’47 Newton has unusual philosophic talent. Despite much Newtonian propaganda for the utility of Newton’s work,48 Hume thinks it is not very useful to the rest of mankind. For Hume there is a moral point of view from which Newton’s achievements have to be re-directed to more praiseworthy aims.49 By contrast, ‘There is no question of importance, whose decision is not compriz’d in the science of man.’50

Moreover, Hume thinks that Newton shares in the superstitious prejudices of his time. While defending the stylistic abilities of King James I, Hume comments: ‘[King James I] has composed a commentary on the Revelations, and proved the pope to be antichrist; may not a similar reproach be extended to the famous writer Napier; and even to Newton, at a time when learning was much more advanced than during the reign of James? From the grossness of its superstitions, we may infer the ignorance of an age; but never should pronounce concerning the folly of an individual, from his admitting popular errors, consecrated by the appearance of religion.’51 Hume thinks that Newton’s writings show that they are the product of an age of religious superstition.52 This criticism of Newton is significant because Hume’s ‘true metaphysics’ is meant as an attack on the ‘considerable part of metaphysics’, which results (in part) ‘from the craft of popular superstitions’.53 Among the many ‘positive advantages, which result from an accurate scrutiny into the powers and faculties of human nature’,54 it serves ‘only to discover larger portions of our ignorance’.55

In this paper, I offer cumulative evidence that Hume is concerned with more substantial parts of Newton’s edifice. Recall that even mathematics, natural philosophy, and natural religion are included among the list of sciences in some measure ‘dependent on the science of man’.56 Thus, if Hume can constrain the authority of natural philosophy, he does not only cut off one pillar of support for the superstitious natural religion fashionable among the learned (typified by Maclaurin),57 but also permits the building of a refashioned and, thus, more useful first philosophy, the ‘science of man’ of the Treatise or the ‘true metaphysics’ of EHU. In the next section, I analyze evidence of the epistemic priority of the ‘science of man’ in Hume.


Proofs of Common Life

In this section I argue that Hume’s fundamental epistemic categories privilege common life and moral philosophy over parts of natural philosophy. I clarify the relationship between Hume’s mitigated scepticism and common life.

Hume distinguishes between three epistemic categories in descending degrees of certainty: ‘demonstrations’, ‘proofs’, and ‘probabilities’.58 It is a bit confusing that sometimes proofs are presented as a species of probabilities, but in context it is clear when he is distinguishing proofs from lesser probabilities. Demonstrations are restricted to relations of ideas, while proofs and probabilities concern matters of fact.59 Claims about ‘objects’ immediately present to the senses and memory can be proved.60 The realm of proof, which can be compared to what other philosophers of the period often call moral certainty,61 involves common sense claims, for example, ‘I see fire burning’; ‘the apple is green’; ‘I recall that it rained on Tuesday’. The mitigated sceptic does not doubt these provable facts from common life.62 Causal reasoning enables claims that go beyond the immediate evidence of the senses or memory; such claims produce probable belief of varying degrees.63 The proofs in the realm of common-life, however, can involve causal claims;64 Hume can claim that he knows ‘with certainty’ that if a friend were to throw himself out of the window, ‘and meet with no obstruction, he will not remain a moment suspended in the air’.65 In order to avoid confusion it is important to emphasize that the certainty involved in ‘proof’ is subjective.66

It is clear that for Hume at least some experimental results in natural philosophy can be part of common life and proven. For example, Hume allows some prism experiments in optics to be a source of very strong ‘proof’.67 Such experiments can produce high epistemic confidence, presumably because the varying experimental effects of the prism, which separates sunlight into different rays, are immediately present to one’s eyes. Hume’s language fits in nicely with the rhetoric of Boyle’s experimentalism, which emphasizes the importance of direct experience.68

Moreover, Hume discusses examples of economic activities as part of common life. For example, when, in the context of the rule of law, even ‘the poorest artificer’ brings goods to market and ‘offers them at a reasonable price’, he can be assured that he will ‘find purchasers’.69 As he did with the result of prism experiments, Hume links experimental reasoning with high epistemic confidence. In his political economy Hume treats causal reasoning, even when ‘abstruse’, as part of common life.70 This is why the language of ‘proof’ appears throughout his political economy.71 In Part I of the Dialogues, even Philo, the arch sceptic, agrees to accept that speculations concerning ‘trade, or morals, or politics, or criticism’ appeal to ‘common sense and experience’ and ‘remove (at least, in part) the suspicion which we so justly entertain with regard to every reasoning that is very subtle and refined’.

So, at least four kinds of ‘matters of fact’ are susceptible to ‘proofs’: (1) claims about objects immediately present to senses and memory; (2) common sense (causal) claims; (3) results of some experiments in natural philosophy, especially if immediately present to eyes; (4) causal claims in moral sciences (e.g., economics and politics).

Common sense and common life plays an important role in the two species of mitigates scepticism.72 In the first ‘common sense and reflection’ are a medicine against pride and dogmatism. Here ‘common sense and reflection’ means being ‘sensible of the strange infirmities of human understanding, even in its most perfect state, and when most accurate and cautious’. Practitioners of the second species of mitigated skepticism (cf. the modest skepticism of the Appendix to the Treatise) will not ‘be tempted to go beyond common life, so long as they consider the imperfection of those faculties which they employ, their narrow reach, and their inaccurate operations’.73

Thus, Hume’s ‘science of man’ emphasizes the weakness of even humanity’s best cognitive capacity and it is at the same time offering an argument for staying within confines of (potential) ordinary experience.74 In fact, mitigated scepticism is said to be ‘nothing but’ reflections of common life ‘methodized and corrected’.75 Hume’s public endorsement of the two species of mitigated scepticism, which like the ‘science of man’, may ‘be … durable and useful’,76 and ‘be of advantage to mankind’77 is not supposed to undermine the reasoning of common life.78 He insists that ‘experimental inference and reasoning concerning the actions of others enters so much into human life, that no man, while awake, is ever a moment without employing it’.79

So, causal claims of metaphysics and even natural philosophy that go beyond common life (e.g., the ‘origin of worlds’) cannot be ‘proven’. This conclusion is anticipated at the start of EHU: ‘The only method of freeing learning, at once, from these abstruse questions, is to enquire seriously into the nature of human understanding, and show, from an exact analysis of its powers and capacity, that it is by no means fitted for such remote and abstruse subjects.’80

One might think81 that mitigated sceptics endorse all of natural philosophy because of two passages. First, Hume asserts that ‘laws of nature’ have been ‘established’ by ‘firm and unalterable experience’.82 There is no evidence that here Hume has Newtonian laws or some other natural philosophy in mind. Rather, in context, the natural reading of ‘laws of nature’ refers to the collective experience of humankind going back to pre-history.83 By contrast, the evidence of, say, universal gravity is based on highly-detailed (and unusual) ‘phenomena’. But, Newton’s ‘phenomena’ are not simple observed events as is clear from a look at the six phenomena Newton lists just after the Rules of Reasoning in Book III. They are best understood as robust empirical generalizations accepted by natural philosophers. (Phenomenon 1 reads, for example: ‘The satellites of Jupiter, by radii drawn to the center of Jupiter, describe areas proportional to the times, and their periodic times—the fixed stars being at rest—are as 3/2 powers of their distances from that center’). They are known to and accepted by only a very narrow part of the collective experience of mankind. Once one understands Newton’s system of the world, it is not easy to overlook how strange his conception of the universe is to common life, even when ‘corrected and methodized’.84 It is hard to see how the collective experience of humankind would establish universal attraction without some extraordinary inferences. In fact, this ‘collective experience’ did not prepare ordinary people or astronomers for Newton’s theory, which was initially welcomed with incredulity even by learned commentators.85 So while the reading I oppose can be sustained on logical grounds, there is only very weak textual and historical evidence for it.86

There is a second passage that causes more problems for my reading: ‘There are some causes, which are entirely uniform and constant in producing a particular effect; and no instance has ever yet been found of any failure or irregularity in their operation. Fire has always burned, and water suffocated every human creature.’ For Hume these are clearly examples of matters of fact based on proof. He then continues, ‘the production of motion by impulse and gravity is an universal law, which has hitherto admitted of no exception’.87 Clearly Hume is inclined to assimilate a law of nature to the category of proof, given that this appears to be a nod to Newton’s famous law that gravity is inversely proportional to distance.88 Yet, Hume’s phrasing is considerably weaker than the statement of Newton’s Inverse-Square Law. Without the phrase ‘universal’ Hume’s comment borders on the banal. And unlike the cases of burning fire and suffocating water, Hume qualifies that the law is exceptionless provisionally. Moreover, against the argument built on either or both passages, ‘Of Miracles’ teaches quite clearly that it is ‘testimony’ that ‘assures’ us of the veracity of the ‘laws of nature’; claims relying on testimony, while provable, can still permit counterbalancing testimony.89

In principle, the ‘science of man’ can be the subject of more reliable knowledge than important parts of natural philosophy. Some parts of natural philosophy can be proven – recall the discussion of prism experiments above – and can be part of common life. For the mitigated sceptic there is a distinction between ‘corrected and methodized’ and, thus, provable common life and claims of lower probability found in the more surprising parts of natural science far removed from common life.90 Hume castigates the greedy embrace by philosophers of theories that have ‘the air of a paradox’, who are, thereby, distancing themselves from the ‘unprejudiced notions of mankind’.91

I have no direct textual evidence for the importance of the distinction between provable common life and claims of lower probability found in natural science in Hume’s philosophy. However, immediately in Part I of the Dialogues, in response to Philo’s very Humean comments, Cleanthes attacks the distinction sharply: ‘the most abstruse and remote objects are those which are best explained by philosophy … In vain would the sceptic make a distinction between science and common life, or between one science and another.’ So Hume is aware that a reading like mine is a natural response to his philosophy.92

I conclude this section by discussing briefly how Hume adapted Newton’s Rules of Reasoning.93 I claim that these rules explain how the mitigated sceptic can correct and methodize common life; they underwrite his ‘proofs’. I then focus on the lacks of equivalence in Hume to Newton’s fourth Rule.

Hume states eight ‘rules by which to judge of causes and effects’. The source of these rules is ambiguous. Although they ‘might have been supply’d by the natural principles of our understanding’,94 Hume provides no evidence for this. Nevertheless, Hume thinks it is ‘proper’ to employ them in his ‘reasoning’.95 Earlier in the Treatise, he was even more adamant about the regulative character of these rules: ‘We shall afterwards take notice of some general rules, by which we ought to regulate our judgment concerning causes and effects; and these rules are form’d on the nature of our understanding, and on our experience of its operations in the judgments we form concerning objects’ (emphasis added).96 So, while these rules may be derived from reflection on how our minds work or some may be derived ‘from experience’,97 they prescribe how we should ascribe causes to ‘objects’ in the world.98 They may be what Hume has in mind in the when he speaks of ‘rules of just reasoning’.99 But on Hume’s definition of a cause, rules 4-8 are at most useful stipulations that help one identify causal relations.100

Hume may have these rules in mind when he describes how the mitigated sceptic corrects and methodizes common life.101 For, the formulation of these rules methodizes common life, while the difficult application of them is frequently a tool in correcting common life by directing our ‘judgment’.102 It is, thus, a way to imagine philosophically what common sense is or should be. To reason ‘justly’ does not, of course, guarantee correctness, but it is the best we can do in common life.103 Hume tacitly relies on the rules throughout his political economy.104 This is prima facie evidence for the conceptual unity of Hume’s thought.

A crucial difference between Hume’s and Newton’s rules is Hume’s lack of an equivalent to Newton’s Rule IV. It reads:

In experimental philosophy, propositions gathered from phenomena by induction should be considered either exactly or very nearly true notwithstanding any contrary hypotheses, until yet other phenomena make such propositions either more exact or liable to exceptions.

This Rule should be followed so that the arguments based on inductions may not be nullified by hypotheses.105

The rule is that we should treat well confirmed propositions as true (or nearly true) until there are deviations that promote new research, which, in turn, lead us to refine our original propositions or reject them for new ones. But while one has a theory, one must not be distracted by possible differing explanations for the found regularities until one has empirical reason. One accepts a theory as true as a means to developing a better theory. As Newton writes in the Preface to the Principia, ‘the principles set down here will shed some light on either this mode of philosophizing or some truer one’ (emphasis added). That is, Newton accepts that physical inquiry is forward-looking and may be open-ended.106 Newton’s Rule IV implicitly accepts that the future may bring surprises and new evidence. Many are right to see in this an anticipation of Hume’s fallibilistic insights;107 it is overlooked, however, that this attitude is in contrast to Hume who had claimed in his interpretation of Newton’s results to know, in advance, what the limits and the ‘ultimate causes and principles which we shall ever discover in nature’, could be.108

Newton’s Rule IV is (1) a proposal of how to treat a theory, that is, as true until proven otherwise.109 It underwrites what I call “Newton’s Challenge” to philosophy. It is also (2) an encouragement to find and exploit known deviations from established regularities in order to make them ‘more exact’. I discuss the second point elsewhere.110 Here I focus on the first.

With only slight anachronism, one can describe Newton’s position as an attitude toward ontic commitment with regard to one’s theory: one is committed to its truth until proven otherwise. While Newton formulates the claim as a research stance, he does not permit a second-order level, as it were, in which alternative hypotheses get a hearing. Hume’s omission of an equivalent rule has several implications. First, without commitment to the truth of a whole “scientific” theory, Hume can appeal to extra-Newtonian criteria in evaluating Newton’s claims. Second, Hume has conceptual space for his distinction between the provable, experimental claims of common life (including parts of natural philosophy), and the lesser, probable commitments of the more abstract parts of natural philosophy. Third, within common life we have natural and habituated principles of association that will make us feel committed to all kinds of things. In common life we can feel moral certitude based on habits. The moral philosopher (if he is a mitigated sceptic) systematizes and corrects these with Hume’s rules of reasoning to generate proofs, but does not have to defer to the natural philosopher.

In this section, I argued that Hume’s epistemic categories underwrite the epistemic priority of the realm of the science of man over natural philosophy, most of which is subject to lesser, probable belief. In the next section, I show that this argument derives support from Hume’s treatment of causation.


Hume’s Causal Anti-Reductionism111

From an explanatory point of view, for Hume the ‘science of man’ is prior or at least equal to the other sciences. In this section I show that Hume’s celebrated treatment of causation undercuts reductionist strategies. First, I offer a distinction between “pre-Newtonian mechanical philosophy” and “Newtonian mechanical philosophy” to remove some common confusion.

Quite diverse thinkers proposed various mechanistic systems and principles. Here I mean this in the broadly pre-Newtonian sense, that is, a view that not only rejects substantial forms and occult qualities, but also expects (hypothetical) explanations to be cast in terms of colliding bodies.112 The rules of their impact become fundamental.113 By 1668/9 Huygens, Wren, and Wallis agreed on the proper mathematical analysis of these, and had created a stable field of enquiry relatively immune from theological and metaphysical argument.114

For Newton, explicitly building on the achievement by Huygens, Wren, and Wallis, by contrast, rational mechanics ‘will be the science, expressed in exact propositions and demonstrations, of the motions that result from any forces whatever and of the forces that are required for any motions whatever.’115 So, we need to be careful to distinguish Newton’s ‘mechanical principles’, which are framed in terms of invisible forces, from the pre-Newtonian sense.116

In the Treatise, Hume quite elegantly analyzes how ‘our’ notion of causality117 – one applying to events that are contiguous, exhibit temporal priority of the cause, and have constant conjunction – is derived from experiencing constant conjunction of objects that produce a union in the imagination.118 Hume’s analysis is a useful first approximation of and unifies what ‘Moderns’ tend to mean by ‘causation’. In his hands, a redefined version of Aristotelian ‘efficient causation’ is the only kind of ‘causation’ available for use.119 There is, thus, a stipulative quality to Hume’s discussion.120 It rules out, for example, the general ‘final causes’ that Newton appeals to in his General Scholium (recall the quotation in the second section of this paper) or the more local final causes that, for example, Colin Maclaurin appeals to in his arguments against Spinoza.121 Hume was by no means the first to attack the four Aristotelian causes; the use of final causes, especially, had been a target for over a century.122

While Hume and Newton both appeal to the authority of ‘experience’, there are tensions between Hume’s account of causation and the contents of Newton’s natural philosophy.123 The behaviour of the moon in its orbit and that of, say, apples falling to the earth have the same cause: namely, the force of gravity, or weight, towards the earth.124 This conflicts with the contiguity requirement, which Hume considers ‘essential’ to causation.125 It is hard to see how contiguity could be made consistent with the universal nature of attraction. The most distant particles of the universe attract each other. More important, the acceleration produced by the exercise of a force is simultaneous with that exercise – thus defying temporal priority. It is hard to see how to make sense of this in light of Hume’s approach, which explicitly attacks the possibility of an effect being simultaneous with its cause.126 Hume claims that the temporal priority of the cause is ‘of no great importance’, yet it appears explicitly or implicitly in all of his definitions of ‘cause’ and his examples.127

It is the great virtue of Hume’s analysis to make clear what several generations of natural philosophers could have presupposed in discussing efficient causes.128 It is no surprise that Hume’s examples – for example the illustration of billiard balls129seem to presuppose something like what has been called a mechanistic world view.130 Of course, Hume’s examples of mental causation obviously are not mechanistic in the pre-Newtonian sense, although he calls ‘instincts … mechanical tendencies’;131 they are about the association of ideas, not bodies.132 Nevertheless, there is a fundamental similarity between Humean causes and pre-Newtonian mechanical causes: they have the same structure, namely, the priority of the cause over the effect, contiguity, and constant conjunction.

The full extent of Hume’s indebtedness to pre-Newtonian mechanical philosophy becomes evident once we realize that he accepts the mechanists’ view of what counts as a proper explanation. Hume writes about the nature of Newton’s achievements: ‘While Newton seemed to draw off the veil from some of the mysteries of nature, he shewed at the same time the imperfections of the mechanical philosophy; and thereby restored her ultimate secrets to that obscurity, in which they ever did and ever will remain’ (emphasis added).133 Hume treats Newton’s refutation of the mechanical philosophy not as a decisive advance in knowledge but, instead, as decisive evidence for the claim that nature will remain unknowable in principle.134 The way to make sense of Hume’s remark is to see that it reveals that he implicitly accepts135 the mechanists’ insistence that theirs was the only program that offered the possibility of intelligible explanation,136 even if it only offered hope of post-facto rational reconstruction.137

Nevertheless, although Hume’s conception of ‘cause’ appears to be inspired by pre-Newtonian mechanical philosophy, as has been shown, from an ontological point of view Hume is not in all things a pre-Newtonian mechanical philosopher. He rejects the reductionism of the mechanical philosophy.138 Hume’s anti-reductionism is made evident by the important assumption in his account of causation that all matters of fact are, in an important sense, alike. In the Treatise, he writes, ‘there is but one kind of necessity, as there is but one kind of cause, and that the common distinction betwixt moral and physical necessity is without any foundation in nature.’139 Moreover, ‘Passions are connected with their objects and with one another; no less than external bodies are connected together. The same relation, then, of cause and effect, which belongs to one, must be common to all of them.’140 Hume thinks that we apply the same type of inference about matters of fact, and that all facts have the same causal structure. In causal explanations there is, thus, no reason to privilege the motion of small bodies or any ‘lower level’ causes. Further evidence for his anti-reductionism comes from Hume’s eight ‘rules by which to judge of causes and effects’ because it is ‘possible for all objects to become causes or effects to each other.’141 Thus, the relative neglect by scholars of Hume’s historical, economic, and political works is odd because these should reveal as much about his views on causation as do those on more ‘philosophic’ topics.

In this section, I argued that Hume’s treatment of causation is anti-reductionist and anti-physicalist. Moreover, his approach to causation is quite general: there is no fundamental difference between natural or moral causes. Within Hume’s epistemology, physical causes need not be prior to moral causes in any sense. Hume’s argument relies on the exclusive claims to intelligibility of the pre-Newtonian mechanical philosophy.142 In this next section I show how Hume rejects Newton’s metaphysics.


Hume’s Rejection of Newton’s Metaphysics143

There is no doubt that Hume respects Newton’s intellectual achievement: ‘The severest scrutiny, which NEWTON’S theory has undergone, proceeded not from his own countrymen, but from foreigners; and if it can overcome the obstacles, which it meets with at present in all parts of Europe, it will probably go down triumphant to the latest posterity.’144 Nevertheless, in this section I give further evidence of Hume’s lack of commitment to Newtonian ontology and methodology. Hume does not only reject the reductionism of pre-Newtonian mechanical philosophers, he also rejects Newton’s claim that forces are a fundamental part of our explanatory framework. Moreover, I show that Hume distinguishes Newton from his followers.

For Hume, we build up our causal theories from experience of particular events.145 This is an important constraint for Hume because it allows him to ask who has ever perceived an instance of a power or force in action – a crucial move for Hume’s attack on theoretical and invisible entities.

It is well known that for Hume all our ideas are derived from impressions.146 Hume’s attacks on inflated claims about substance, essence, force, power, and – most importantly – God, all rely on his rhetorically-powerful ability to ask to what impression such notions can be traced.147 For, ‘[i]deas always represent the objects or impressions, from which they are derived.’148 This has become known as the ‘copy principle’. If no such ‘external’ objects or impressions are to be found, then we must conclude that such ideas are the product of ‘internal’ ‘passions and emotions’, a ‘trivial suggestion of the fancy’, or ‘some imperfection in [the] faculties [of mind]’.149 The thrust of Hume’s account is to make talk of, say, substance or force (power, God, etc.) seem either meaningless or restricted to the particular qualities of bodies from which the idea is derived.150 At best, they have reference to ‘an effect, or some other event constantly conjoined with’ the cause.151 As Hume says in a late addition to the Treatise, we must ‘confine our speculations to the appearances of objects to our senses, without entering into disquisitions concerning their real nature and operations’.152 This imperative is, in fact, for Hume not derived from Newton, but the ‘Newtonian philosophy…rightly understood’ (emphasis in original).153 Newton’s speculations in the last paragraph of the General Scholium about ‘a certain very subtle spirit pervading gross bodies and lying hidden in them’, or Newton’s posthumously-published relational account of gravity as an inessential property of matter,154 may well have been Hume’s targets.

Hume’s approach to natural philosophy means that when the sciences talk about forces or powers, these words must be reinterpreted.155 According to Hume ‘force’ and ‘power’ have, at most, a reference to ‘an effect, or some other event’. And ‘Force, Power, Energy … [these] words, as commonly used, have very loose meanings annexed to them; and their ideas are very uncertain and confused’.156 Hume denies here the fundamental achievement of the Principia.157 What Hume refuses to accept is that Newton’s achievement shows that the ‘pre-Newtonian’ mechanical philosophy offers a false choice between hypothetical reconstructions in terms of colliding bodies or no explanations at all.

In fact, despite Newton’s abhorrence of hypotheses, Hume is eager to propose and discuss his hypotheses in his ‘science of man’.158 Hume’s willingness to introduce and describe hypotheses in his main argument brings him closer to, say, Boyle’s methodology.159

In the Treatise, Hume makes no obvious move in the direction of deriving the basic principles of, say, physics, from his theory of human nature. He is quite explicit: ‘this belongs not to my present purpose’. He thinks it is ‘beyond the reach of human understanding’ to ‘penetrate into the nature of bodies, or explain the secret causes of their operations’. He cannot ‘approve’ of the ambition to go beyond knowing bodies by their external properties.160 For Hume, ‘we have no idea of substance, distinct from that of a collection of particular qualities’.161

One may think that Hume was inspired by Newton’s (Lockean) remarks in the General Scholium to the Principia (in the context of a discussion of our knowledge of God’s attributes): ‘In bodies we see only their figures and colours, we hear only the sounds, we touch only their outward surfaces, we smell only the smells, and taste the savours; but their inward substances are not to be known, either by our senses or by any reflex act of our minds: much less, then, have we any idea of the substance of God.’162 Hume and Newton agree that our inquiries should be guided by experienced properties of bodies; they agree that we can have no knowledge of what Newton calls ‘innermost’ substances (or Lockean real essences). The General Scholium may have been the textual source for Hume’s claim (quoted before) about Newton restoring nature’s ‘ultimate secrets to that obscurity, in which they ever did and ever will remain’.163 Yet, Newton’s position is less constraining than Hume’s. For, while substances are not known to us by our senses or by reflection, Newton does not rule out that future inquiry may give us some access to ideas of such substances as is hinted at by his claim about having ‘much less’ an idea of the substance of God. Newton’s words imply that in principle we can at least know something about the features of our ignorance about the ideas of substances of bodies and perhaps learn something positive about invisible properties associated with bodies with Newton’s method of inquiry.164 Newton’s General Scholium obscures that Newton’s natural philosophy has no need for a notion of substance – the concept does no work in the Principia and Opticks.165 Newton’s pessimism about our ability to possess ideas of innermost substances is not evidence of general scepticism about knowledge of nature, but rather a change in how to conceive what knowledge of nature is about: the (Newtonian) ‘mechanical principles’ centring on the discovery of nature’s forces and the original and connate properties of bodies.

Moreover, in the final paragraph of the General Scholium, Newton hints at a program of research, perhaps inspired by the success of Francis Hauksbee’s electrical experiments, to penetrate into the nature of matter.166 This program was by no means finished by the time of Newton’s death. As my discussion of Newton’s Rule IV indicates, it is characteristic of Newton’s willingness to think of his results as programmatic for further research. This attitude is even apparent in Newton’s famous lines in the General Scholium when he admits about his treatment of gravity that he has ‘not yet assigned a cause to it’ and that he has ‘not as yet been able to deduce from phenomena the reason for these properties of gravity’167 (emphasis added).

One may think that Hume’s use of ‘Newtonian philosophy’ in the Treatise suggests that Hume has described Newton’s natural philosophy (as understood by Hume). But this is not likely because elsewhere he writes: ‘It was never the meaning of Sir ISAAC NEWTON to rob second causes of all force or energy; though some of his followers have endeavoured to establish that theory upon his authority.’168 So, first, Hume’s Newton accepts some real causes in nature;169 Hume’s Newton is neither a sceptic about causation nor an occasionalist (Leibniz had raised this concern in his exchange with Clarke). Second, Hume is careful to distinguish Newton from the Newtonians.170 Elsewhere, in the context of a discussion of the doctrine of occasionalism, Hume emphasizes the differences between Newton and the Newtonians again: ‘Sir Isaac Newton (tho’ some of his Followers have taken a different Turn of thinking) plainly rejects it, by substituting the Hypothesis of an Ætheral Fluid, not the immediate Volition of the Deity, as the Cause of Attraction.’171

Thus, a more likely interpretation is that Hume believes he has offered a prescriptive interpretation of how Newtonian philosophy should be viewed in light of the results of his ‘science of man’, which shows the limitations of our cognitive capacity, and his restrictive form of Empiricism which contribute to his ‘modest’ or mitigated scepticism. Hume is aware that Newton’s universe is filled with invisible interactive causal forces. He sees himself as arguing that the authority of experience does not require us to accept Newton’s own understanding of his achievement.172
Conclusion: Hume’s attitude toward Newton’s impact on philosophy

Hume and Newton both appeal to the authority of experience; it is their shared ‘foundation’.173 Nevertheless, the copy principle, what is known as the separability principle,174 and Hume’s ‘rules of reasoning’, guide how Hume believes ‘experience’ should be analyzed. Hume’s Newton has shown merely the road to the ‘true philosophy’.175 One way to understand Hume’s self-understanding of the ‘science of man’ is to see it, then, as the fulfillment of the Newtonian philosophy ‘rightly understood’ – that is, of course, by Hume.176

Hume’s unified account of causation is a rejection of Newtonian final causes, Newtonian simultaneous causes, and the foundational priority of natural philosophy. Hume may have thought that his unified and restrictive account of causation relieved him of the need to offer the kind of detail we find in, for example, Berkeley’s analysis of natural philosophy.177 Of course, Hume does offer some guidance on how to interpret aspects of mathematics and natural philosophy.178 Perhaps, a more detailed account would have been offered in a work mentioned in his correspondence, ‘Considerations previous to Geometry and Natural Philosophy’, now lost.179

I argued that major currents in Hume’s philosophy can be read as a (tacit) attack on the authority of Newton’s philosophy. First, they have potentially negative religious consequences; second they are not useful if not appropriately re-interpreted.180 Third, Hume may be responding to “Newton’s Challenge”. Here I expand briefly on the third.

As Cleanthes points out, in Hume’s time it has become a sign of severe ignorance to oppose natural philosophy: ‘even monks and inquisitors are now constrained to withdraw their opposition [to Copernicanism]’.181 Maclaurin, for example, argues from the empirical success and authority of Newtonian natural philosophy to rejection of alternative positions, methodologies, and foundations within philosophy. Yet, by Hume’s lights, many crucial elements of Newton’s natural philosophy do not have a proper foundation. While offering the perspective of the ‘abstract’ philosophy in, Hume writes that it is a ‘reproach’ that ‘philosophy should not yet have fixed, beyond the controversy, the foundations of morals, reasoning, and criticism’.182 The context suggests that the foundation would be the ‘source of … distinctions’ for ‘truth and falsehood, vice and virtue, beauty and deformity’.

It is worth recalling that Hume starts the Treatise with the following observation: ‘philosophy’ seems to have ‘drawn disgrace’ upon ‘itself’. There is widespread ‘prejudice against metaphysical reasonings of all kinds’.183 Only after articulating this state of malaise surrounding and within philosophy does Hume offer the science of man as a ‘foundation’ for the other sciences. Hume’s attack on Newton’s authority is thus connected to his general attempt to resurrect the prestige and independence of a reinterpreted and morally constrained first philosophy. My paper explains Hume’s otherwise puzzling passage: ‘religion, and politics, and consequently metaphysics and morals. All these form the most considerable branches of science. Mathematics and natural philosophy … are not half so valuable.’184

Hume’s ambitions for the science of man are grander and more controversial than his many admirers and critics realize. Hume offers what he takes to be a useful and virtuous philosophy that can regulate Newtonian natural philosophy. Oddly enough the simultaneously-enduring successes of science and Hume’s account of causation are to blame for the state of affairs that makes Hume’s aims so difficult to see for us. Hume’s stipulative account of causation narrowed the possible space in which reflection on the sciences by philosophers and scientists alike was to take place. We take the terms with which he redefined the problem so much for granted, it is difficult for us to evaluate his attempted lasting contributions, regardless of their merits, to philosophy.

Eric Schliesser,



Ghent University



 This paper has its origin in a chapter of my dissertation drafted in 2000. Material from it has been presented under various titles in a large number of workshops and conferences; I have incurred countless intellectual debts along the way. Special thanks to Dan Garber, Charles Larmore, Howard Stein, Ian Mueller, Lisa Downing, Sam Fleischacker, Allesandro Pajewski, William Vanderburgh, Leonidas Montes, Abe Stone, Christopher Berry, Ursula Goldenbaum, Joe La Porte, Carl Craver, Cindy Schossberger, Don Baxter, Rachel Zuckert, Steffen Ducheyne, Sarah Brouillette, Peter Millican, Stephen Snobelen, and Graciella de Pierris for very helpful comments on earlier drafts and audiences at Mid-Atlantic Seminar in Early Modern Philosophy (2004) at Rutgers, NJ, especially John Hawthorne, and Sean Greenberg; audiences at Syracuse University (2005), especially Jose Benardete, Andre Gallois, and Eric Hiddleston; the University of Chicago (2005), especially Bill Tait and Michael Greene; the University of Utah, especially Lex Newman and Steve Downes; The Hume Society (2005), especially my commentator, Saul Traiger; the History of Science Society (2006), where Dan Garber enjoyed calling attention to the changes in my views. Finally, I warmly thank all the diligent and generous anonymous referees, especially, for this journal.

1 Robert H Hurlbutt, Hume, Newton, and the design argument (Lincoln, 1985, revised edn.).

2 Forerunners of aspects of my view can be found in S K Wertz, ‘Hume and the Historiography of Science’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 54 (1993), 411-36; and Wayne Waxman ‘The Psychologistic Foundations of Hume’s Critique of Mathematical Philosophy’, Hume Studies, 22 (1996), 123-68. Yoram Hazony, ‘Hume’s Program as an Alternative to Naturalism in Contemporary Epistemology and Philosophy of Mind’, presented at Hume Society, Halifax, 2009, discerns much of the same position in Hume.

3 David Hume, An enquiry concerning human understanding (EHU), ed. Tom L Beauchamp (Oxford, 1999), 1.12. I quote Hume from the following editions: A treatise of human nature (Treatise), ed. David Fate Norton and Mary J Norton (Oxford, 2007); Essays, moral, political, and literary (EMPL), ed. with foreword, notes and glossary by Eugene F Miller (Indianapolis, 1985, revised edn.); An enquiry concerning the principles of morals (EPM), ed. Tom L Beauchamp (Oxford, 1998); Dialogues concerning natural religion (Dialogues), ed. with intro. and notes by Martin Bell (London, 1990); The history of England (History), (6 vols., Indianapolis, 1983); and The natural history of religion (Natural history), ed. with intro. by James Fieser (New York, 1992).

4 Hume, Treatise, 1.1.1.12ff.

5 I use Hume’s phrases, ‘science of man’, ‘science of human nature’, and ‘moral philosophy’ as rough synonyms, meaning in our terminology, ‘social science’ in a very broad sense. I use ‘natural philosophy’ as a broad synonym for what we tend to call ‘physical science’.

6 See also Louis E Loeb, Stability and justification in Hume’s Treatise (Oxford, 2002).

7 See, e.g., James Force, ‘Hume’s Interest in Newton and Science’, Hume Studies, 13 (1987), 180-7, which provides an excellent overview of different approaches to understanding the relationship between Hume and Newton. See also Graciela De Pierris, ‘Causation as a Philosophic Relation in Hume’, Philosophy and Phenomological Research, 64 (2002), 499-545; and Barry Stroud, Hume (London and New York, 1977), chapter 1. In their debate over the New Hume, included in Reading Hume on human understanding, ed. Peter Millican (Oxford, 2002), both Galen Strawson, ‘David Hume: Objects and Power’, 237, 245, 247, 249, 251, 256 n. 46, and Simon Blackburn, ‘Hume and Thick Connexions’, 266, appeal to Hume as a follower of Newton. For a corrective see Michael Barfoot, ‘Hume and The culture of Science in the Early Eighteenth Century’, Studies in the philosophy of the Scottish Enlightenment, ed. M A Stewart (Oxford, 1990).

8 Hume, Treatise, 1.3.15.

9 Hume, Treatise, 1.4.6.23.

10 See, e.g., Norman Kemp Smith, The philosophy of David Hume, (London, 1941), 53-62, 550, and 559 n. 1; James Noxon, Hume’s philosophical development: a study of his methods (Oxford, 1973); and De Pierris, ‘Causation as a Philosophic Relation in Hume’. Nicholas Capaldi, David Hume, the Newtonian philosopher (Boston, 1975), stakes out the most extreme position of this kind. My dissertation, ‘Indispensable Hume: from Isaac Newton’s natural philosophy to Adam Smith’s science of man’ (PhD diss., University of Chicago, 2002), also reflects this orientation.

11 Hume, Treatise, 1.1.4.6; see, e.g., David Owen, Hume’s reason (Oxford, 1999), 77-8. Cf. Jerry A Fodor, Hume variations (Oxford, 2006), 121-3.

12 Janet Broughton, ‘Hume’s Ideas about Necessary Connection’, Hume Studies, 13 (1987), 217-44; Martin Bell, ‘Hume and Causal Power: The Influence of Malebranche and Newton’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 5 (1997), 67-86; Kenneth P Winkler, ‘The New Hume’, in The new Hume debate, ed. Rupert Read and Kenneth A Richman (London, 2000), 52-87, move beyond the strategy of noticing similar metaphors by describing what they take to be the parallel nature of Newton’s and Hume’s positions; they then use these parallels to resolve interpretive disputes about Hume.

13 1.15.

14 Stephen Buckle, Hume’s Enlightenment tract: the unity and purpose of an enquiry concerning human understanding (Oxford, 2001).

15 See Howard Stein, ‘On Philosophy and Natural Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 18 (1993), 177-201. See also Eric Schliesser, ‘Hume’s Missing Shade of Blue Reconsidered from a Newtonian Perspective’, Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 2 (2004), 164-75. For an earlier version, see P Jones, Hume’s sentiments: their Ciceronian and French context (Edinburgh, 1982), 12-13.

16 John Earman, Hume’s abject failure: the argument against miracles (Oxford, 2002) 47, calls Hume’s arguments ‘blunderbuss’ and his conception of inductive inference ‘impoverished’. See also James Franklin, ‘Achievements and Fallacies in Hume’s Account of Infinite Divisibility’, Hume Studies, 20 (1994), 85-102.

17 See section 3 of Eric Schliesser ‘Hume’s Newtonianism and Anti-Newtonianism’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edn. Winter, 2008), ed. Edward N Zalta, URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ win2008/entries/hume-newton/. On the method analysis and synthesis in Newton, see G E Smith, ‘The Methodology of the Principia’, in The Cambridge companion to Isaac Newton, ed. I B Cohen and G E Smith (Cambridge, 2002), 138-73; and Leonidas Montes, Adam Smith in context: a critical reassessment of some central components of his thought (Basingstoke, 2004), 132-44.

18 Graciela De Pierris, ‘Hume and Locke on Scientific Methodology: The Newtonian Legacy’, Hume Studies, 32 (2006), 320.

19 Dale Jacquette, ‘Hume on the Infinite Divisibility of Extension and Exact Geometrical Values’, in New essays on David Hume, ed. Emilio Mazza and Emanuele Ronchetti (Milan, 2008), 81. Cf. Eric Schliesser, ‘Critical Notice of New Essays on David Hume edited by Mazza et al.’, Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 6 (2008), 203-8.

20 Martin Bell, ‘Hume and Causal Power: The Influence of Malebranche and Newton’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 5 (1997), 67-86. Bell calls attention to how the language of EHU is more Newtonian than the Treatise. Given that Hume ascribed the relative failure of the Treatise to its rhetoric (see ‘Advertisement’ to EHU), it makes sense for him to appeal more to public prejudice among the educated in favour of Newtonianism after 1740. For more on Hume’s changes, see Eric Schliesser, ‘Two Definitions of Causation, Normativity, and Hume’s Debate with Newton’, in Future perspectives on Newton scholarship and the Newtonian legacy in Eighteenth-century science and philosophy, ed. Steffen Ducheyne (Brussels, 2009), 47-69.

21 See Eric Schliesser and George E Smith, ‘Huygens’ 1688 Report to the Directors of the Dutch East India Company on the Measurement of Longitude at Sea and the Evidence it Offered Against Universal Gravity’, Archive for the History of the Exact Sciences, forthcoming; and K Maglo, ‘The Reception of Newton’s Gravitational Theory by Huygens, Varignon, and Maupertuis: How Normal Science may be Revolutionary’, Perspectives on Science, 11 (2003), 135-69.

22 Adam Smith, Essays on philosophical subjects, ed. W P D Wightman and J C Bryce, vol. III of The Glasgow edition of the works and correspondence of Adam Smith (Indianapolis, 1982), section IV: ‘The History of Astronomy’. See Eric Schliesser, ‘Realism in the Face of Scientific Revolutions: Adam Smith on Newton’s “Proof” of Copernicanism’, British Journal of the History of Philosophy, 13 (2005), 687-732.

23 This was Locke’s position to his death. See Mary Domski, ‘Locke’s Qualified Embrace of Newton’s Principia’, in Interpreting Newton, ed. A Janiak and E Schliesser, Cambridge, in press.

24 Lorne Falkenstein, ‘Hume on “Genuine”, “True”, and “Rational” Religion’, Eighteenth-Century Thought, ed. James G Buickerood, 4 (2008), 171-201 offers a careful analysis of Hume’s publication history and reconciles apparent inconsistencies in Hume’s stance on religion.

25 See Kemp Smith, The philosophy of David Hume, 58-62 or Buckle, Hume’s Enlightenment tract, 70ff.

26 For example, see Newton’s fourth Rule of Reasoning, which was added to third edition, quoted in body of text. Newton also uses the phrase ‘experimental philosophy’ in the General Scholium to the Principia (added to second edition of 1713). See Alan Shapiro, ‘Newton’s Experimental Philosophy’, Early Modern Science and Medicine, 9 (2004), 185-217.

27 De Pierris, ‘Hume and Locke on Scientific Methodology’, 320.

28 For more on this see the section on Hume’s experimentalism at: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hume-newton/#Exp. The experimental method of Boyle and Newton are often lumped together, e.g., Buckle, Hume’s Enlightenment tract, 82.

29 See, e.g., the discussion of George Turnbull’s The principles of moral and Christian philosophy in Paul Wood ‘Thomas Reid and the Tree of the Sciences’, Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 2 (2004), 124-5.

30 Newton, Opticks, or a treatise of the reflections, refractions, inflections and colours of light (4th ed., 1730; New York, 1952), 405.This is not to say that Newton would have expressed his full views; on Newton’s esotericism, see S Snobelen, ‘To Discourse of God: Isaac Newton’s Heterodox Theology and his Natural Philosophy’, Science and Dissent in England, 1688-1945, ed. Paul Wood (Aldershot, 2004), 39-65.

31 See Howard Stein, ‘Newton’s Metaphysics’, in The Cambridge companion to Newton, 261. See also Hurlbutt, Hume, Newton, and the design argument, which is still quite useful. I quote from Isaac Newton, The principia: mathematical principles of natural philosophy, trans. I Bernard Cohen, Anne Whitman and Julia Budenz (3rd ed., 1726; Berkeley, 1999), 943. In Hume’s Dialogues (Part II), Cleanthes concedes that the a posteriori argument offers probable evidence.

32 Newton, Principia, 942; Andrew Cunningham, ‘Getting the Game Right: Some Plain Words on the Identity and Invention of Science’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 19 (1988), 365-89; idem, ‘How the Principia Got Its Name; Or, Taking Natural Philosophy Seriously’, History of Science, 29 (1991), 377-92. Cunningham, along with Andrew Janiak in his Newton as philosopher (Cambridge, 2008), claim that Newton’s physics presupposes his theology. See also G A J Rogers, ‘Newton and the Guaranteeing God’, in Newton and Religion: context, nature and influence, ed. James E Force and Richard H Popkin (Dordrecht, 1999), 221-37.

33 Newton, Principia, 942.

34 See also Eric Schliesser, ‘The Newtonian Refutation of Spinoza’, in Interpreting Newton, in press and idem, ‘Newton’s Challenge to Philosophy’, unpublished typescript.

35 Hume, Treatise, Intro., 4-7. In this ‘Introduction’ Hume inverts Descartes’ tree of the sciences; the roots are not metaphysics as Descartes thought, but a theory of human nature. See John Passmore, Hume’s intentions (London, 1968), 12. Hume follows Locke and Malebranche in emphasizing the importance of a science of man.

36 Hume, Treatise, Intro., 6. Thomas Reid caught some of this spirit in the opening paragraph of a work otherwise deeply critical of Hume: ‘The human mind is curious and wonderful ... a subject highly worthy of inquiry on its own account, but still more worthy on account of the extensive influence which the knowledge of it hath over every other branch of science’ (Chapter 1, Section I of An inquiry into the human mind: or the principles of common sense). In a Humean vein, Reid talks about an ‘anatomy of the mind’ (12) in the same section.

37 Hume, Treatise, Intro., 4; emphasis added.

38 See Hurlbutt, Hume, Newton, and the design argument, especially chapters 1 and 9, and Buckle, Hume’s Enlightenment tract, chapters 2-3.

Directory: 5382

Download 235.38 Kb.

Share with your friends:
  1   2   3




The database is protected by copyright ©essaydocs.org 2023
send message

    Main page